aboutsummaryrefslogtreecommitdiff
path: root/books/psicologia/psychology-of-intelligence.md
diff options
context:
space:
mode:
authorSilvio Rhatto <rhatto@riseup.net>2018-08-07 10:05:58 -0300
committerSilvio Rhatto <rhatto@riseup.net>2018-08-07 10:05:58 -0300
commitb6c0ffcaf707ee1968a7f29021d20357692a84d0 (patch)
treebb1ec89dce7ca4072fdfa794e3492b71ef93ff94 /books/psicologia/psychology-of-intelligence.md
parent180d1f6ebc346308df7f84150604a100f18118f9 (diff)
downloadblog-b6c0ffcaf707ee1968a7f29021d20357692a84d0.tar.gz
blog-b6c0ffcaf707ee1968a7f29021d20357692a84d0.tar.bz2
Reorganization
Diffstat (limited to 'books/psicologia/psychology-of-intelligence.md')
-rw-r--r--books/psicologia/psychology-of-intelligence.md332
1 files changed, 0 insertions, 332 deletions
diff --git a/books/psicologia/psychology-of-intelligence.md b/books/psicologia/psychology-of-intelligence.md
deleted file mode 100644
index be516af..0000000
--- a/books/psicologia/psychology-of-intelligence.md
+++ /dev/null
@@ -1,332 +0,0 @@
-[[!meta title="The Psychology of Intelligence"]]
-
-* Author: Jean Piaget.
-* Publisher: Routledge Classics.
-* Year: 1950.
-
-## References
-
-* [Piaget's theory of cognitive development - Wikipedia](https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Piaget's_theory_of_cognitive_development).
-
-## Overview
-
-This overview is a mixed of both ideas from the book altogether with other
-considerations I've got by reading other, related material:
-
-### Intelligence is reversible!
-
-As what's really wonderful about this reversibility is that it's built atop of
-lower, fundamental levels of irreversible dynamical systems.
-
-That revesibility is the capacity to the adaptive system do turn away from
-configurations that doesn't lead to a defined goal and replace by other
-pathways, mixing introspection and empirism.
-
-Reading this book along with The Tree of Live from Maturana and Varella
-and Morin's Method I get the feeling that intelligence in life arises from
-the sensori-motor system and gets deeper in a process where the nervous
-system inflates to give way to impulses/stimuli that originates from itself.
-
-Consequential to this reversibility is that intelligence might experimentation
-freely without risking itself producing damages or permanent harm to itself,
-which is different to say that somebody can't harm him/herself by the consequence
-of his/her acts.
-
-Also, while what happens with intelligence looks entirely reversible, mind is
-not composed of intelligence alone. Other instances exist that might put the
-whole apparatus on restricted modes of operation, such when in a neurosis which
-is a state of constant looping in a given theme.
-
-## Misc
-
-* Perception (imediate contact with the world) (127).
-
-* Habit: beyond short and rapidly automatised connections between per-
- ceptions and responses (habit) (127).
-
-* How the whole body is seem according to his theory? There's a movement (sic)
- where intelligence raises from the sensori-motor to the mind, but can we
- consider the other way as well, about what's conceived by abstract thought
- be then used as a source of sensori-motor intelligence? I guess so, but wonder
- how that could be articulated in Piaget's theory.
-
-## Intelligence and equilibrium
-
- Then, if intelligence is thus conceived as the form of equilibrium towards
- which all cognitive processes tend, there arises the problem of its relations
- with perception (Chap. 3), and with habit (Chap. 4).
-
- -- Preface
-
- Every response, whether it be an act directed towards the outside world or an
- act internalized as thought, takes the form of an adaptation or, better, of a
- re-adaptation. The individual acts only if he experiences a need, i.e., if the
- equilibrium between the environment and the organism is momentarily upset, and
- action tends to re-establish the equilibrium, i.e., to re-adapt the organ- ism
- (Claparède). A response is thus a particular case of inter- action between the
- external world and the subject, but unlike physiological interactions, which
- are of a material nature and involve an internal change in the bodies which are
- present, the responses studied by psychology are of a functional nature and are
- achieved at greater and greater distances in space (percep- tion, etc.) and in
- time (memory, etc.) besides following more and more complex paths (reversals,
- detours, etc.). Behaviour, thus conceived in terms of functional interaction,
- presupposes two essential and closely interdependent aspects: an affective
- aspect and a cognitive aspect.
-
- -- 5
-
- Furthermore, intelligence itself does not consist of an isolated and sharply
- differentiated class of cognitive processes. It is not, properly speaking, one
- form of structuring among others; it is the form of equilibrium towards which
- all the structures arising out of perception, habit and elementary
- sensori-motor mechan- isms tend. It must be understood that if intelligence is
- not a faculty this denial involves a radical functional continuity between the
- higher forms of thought and the whole mass of lower types of cognitive and
- motor adaptation; so intelligence can only be the form of equilibrium towards
- which these tend.
-
- This does not mean, of course, that a judgment consists of a co- ordination of
- perceptual structures, or that perceiving means unconscious inference (although
- both these theories have been held), for functional continuity in no way
- excludes diversity or even heterogeneity among structures. Every structure is
- to be thought of as a particular form of equilibrium, more or less stable
- within its restricted field and losing its stability on reach- ing the limits of
- the field. But these structures, forming different levels, are to be regarded as
- succeeding one another according to a law of development, such that each one
- brings about a more inclusive and stable equilibrium for the processes that
- emerge from the preceding level. Intelligence is thus only a generic term to
- indicate the superior forms of organization or equilibrium of cognitive
- structurings.
-
- -- 7
-
- In general, we may thus conclude that there is an essential unity between the
- sensori-motor processes that engender per- ceptual activity, the formation of
- habits, and pre-verbal or pre- representative intelligence itself. The latter
- does not therefore arise as a new power, superimposed all of a sudden on com-
- pletely prepared previous mechanisms, but is only the expres- sion of these
- same mechanisms when they go beyond present and immediate contact with the
- world (perception), as well as beyond short and rapidly automatised connections
- between per- ceptions and responses (habit), and operate at progressively
- greater distances and by more complex routes, in the direction of mobility and
- reversibility. Early intelligence, therefore, is simply the form of mobile
- equilibrium towards which the mechanisms adapted to perception and habit tend;
- but the latter attain this only by leaving their respective fields of
- application. Moreover, intelligence, from this first sensori-motor stage
- onwards, has already succeeded in constructing, in the special case of space,
- the equilibrated structure that we call the group of displacements—in an
- entirely empirical or practical form, it is true, and of course remaining on
- the very restricted plane of immediate space. But it goes without saying that
- this organiza- tion, circumscribed as it is by the limitations of action, still
- does not constitute a form of thought. On the contrary, the whole development
- of thought, from the advent of language to the end of childhood, is necessary
- in order that the completed sensori- motor structures, which may even be
- co-ordinated in the form of empirical groups, may be extended into genuine
- operations, which will constitute or reconstruct these groupings and groups at
- the level of symbolic behaviour and reflective reasoning.
-
- -- 127-128
-
-## Logic and psychology
-
- An axiomatics is an exclusively hypothetico-deductive sci-
- ence, i.e., it reduces to a minimum appeals to experience (it even
- aims to eliminate them entirely) in order freely to reconstruct its
- object by means of undemonstrable propositions (axioms),
- which are to be combined as rigorously as possible and in every
- possible way. In this way geometry has made great progress,
- seeking to liberate itself from all intuition and constructing the
- most diverse spaces simply by defining the primary elements to
- be admitted by hypothesis and the operations to which they are
- subject. The axiomatic method is thus the mathematical method
- par excellence and it has had numerous applications, not only in
- pure mathematics, but in various fields of applied mathematics
- (from theoretical physics to mathematical economics). The use-
- fulness of an axiomatics, in fact, goes beyond that of demonstra-
- tion (although in this field it constitutes the only rigorous
- method); in the face of complex realities, resisting exhaustive
- analysis, it permits us to construct simplified models of reality
- and thus provides the study of the latter with irreplaceable dis-
- secting instruments. To sum up, an axiomatics constitutes a “pat-
- tern” for reality, as F. Gonseth has clearly shown, and, since all
- abstraction leads to a schematization, the axiomatic method in
- the long run extends the scope of intelligence itself.
-
- But precisely because of its “schematic” character, an axiomat-
- ics cannot claim to be the basis of, and still less to replace, its
- corresponding experimental science, i.e. the science relating to
- that sector of reality for which the axiomatics forms the pattern.
- Thus, axiomatic geometry is incapable of teaching us what the
- space of the real world is like (and “pure economics” in no way
- exhausts the complexity of concrete economic facts). No axi-
- omatics could replace the inductive science which corresponds
- to it, for the essential reason that its own purity is merely a limit
- which is never completely attained. As Gonseth also says, there
- always remains an intuitive residue in the most purified pattern
- (just as there is already an element of schematization in all intu-
- ition). This reason alone is enough to show why an axiomatics
- will never be the basis of an experimental science and why there
- is an experimental science corresponding to every axiomatics
- (and, no doubt, vice versa).
-
- -- page 30
-
- It is true that in addition to the individual consistency of
- actions there enter into thought interactions of a collective order
- and consequently “norms” imposed by this collaboration. But
- co-operation is only a system of actions, or of operations, car-
- ried out in concert, and we may repeat the preceding argument
- for collective symbolic behaviour, which likewise remains at a
- level containing real structures, unlike axiomatizations of a
- formal nature.
-
- For psychology, therefore, there remains unaltered the prob-
- lem of understanding the mechanism with which intelligence
- comes to construct coherent structures capable of operational
- combination; and it is no use invoking “principles” which this
- intelligence is supposed to apply spontaneously, since logical
- principles concern the theoretical pattern formulated after
- thought has been constructed and not this living process of con-
- struction itself. Brunschvicg has made the profound observation
- that intelligence wins battles or indulges, like poetry, in a con-
- tinuous work of creation, while logico-mathematical deduction
- is comparable only to treatises on strategy and to manuals of
- “poetic art”, which codify the past victories of action or mind
- but do not ensure their future conquests. 1
-
- -- page 34
-
-## Habit and sensori-motor intelligence
-
-Circular reaction:
-
- Let us imagine an infant in a cradle with a raised cover from which
- hang a whole series of rattles and a loose string. The child grasps
- this and so shakes the whole arrangement without expecting to do
- so or understanding any of the detailed spatial or causal rela-
- tions. Surprised by the result, he reaches for the string and
- carries out the whole sequence several times over. J. M. Baldwin
- called this active reproduction of a result at first obtained by
- chance a “circular reaction”. The circular reaction is thus a typ-
- ical example of reproductive assimilation. The first movement
- executed and followed by its result constitutes a complete action,
- which creates a new need once the objects to which it relates
- have returned to their initial stage; these are then assimilated to
- the previous action (thereby promoted to the status of a schema)
- which stimulates its reproduction, and so on. Now this mechan-
- ism is identical with that which is already present at the source
- of elementary habits except that, in their case, the circular reac-
- tion affects the body itself (so we will give the name “primary
- circular reaction” to that of the early level, such as the schema of
- thumb-sucking), whereas thenceforward, thanks to prehension,
- it is applied to external objects (we will call this behaviour affect-
- ing objects the “secondary circular reaction,” although we must
- remember that these are not yet by any means conceived as
- substances by the child).
-
- -- 110-112
-
-Early intelligence:
-
- The routes between the subject and the object fol-
- lowed by action, and also by sensori-motor reconstitutions and
- anticipations, are no longer direct and simple pathways as at the
- previous stages: rectilinear as in perception, or stereotyped and
- uni-directional as in circular reactions. The routes begin to vary
- and the utilisation of earlier schemata begins to extend further in
- time. This is characteristic of the connection between means and
- ends, which henceforth are differentiated, and this is why we
- may begin to speak of true intelligence. But, apart from the
- continuity that links it with earlier behaviour, we should note the
- limitations of this early intelligence: there are no inventions or
- discoveries of new means, but simply application of known
- means to unforeseen circumstances.
-
- -- 114
-
-Innovation:
-
- Two acquisitions characterise the next stage, both relating to
- the utilisation of past experience. The assimilatory schemata so
- far described are of course continually accommodated to
- external data. But this accommodation is, so to speak, suffered
- rather than sought; the subject acts according to his needs and
- this action either harmonizes with reality or encounters resist-
- ances which it tries to overcome. Innovations which arise for-
- tuitously are either neglected or else assimilated to previous
- schemata and reproduced by circular reaction. However, a time
- comes when the innovation has an interest of its own, and this
- certainly implies a sufficient stock of schemata for comparisons
- to be possible and for the new fact to be sufficiently like the
- known one to be interesting and sufficiently different to avoid
- satiation. Circular reaction, then, will consist of a reproduction
- of the new phenomenon, but with variations and active
- experimentation that are intended precisely to extract from it its
- new possibilities.
-
- -- 114
-
-Topology:
-
- But there now arises a problem whose discussion leads to the study of space.
- Perceptual constancy is the product of simple regulations and we saw (Chap. 3)
- that the absence at all ages of absolute constancy and the existence of adult
- “superconstancy” provide evidence for the regulative rather than operational
- char- acter of the system. There is, therefore, all the more reason why it
- should be true of the first two years. Does not the construction of space, on
- the other hand, lead quite rapidly to a grouping structure and even a group
- structure in accordance with
-
- Poincaré’s famous hypothesis concerning the psychologically primary influence of
- the “group of displacements?” The genesis of space in sensori-motor
- intelligence is com- pletely dominated by the progressive organisation of
- responses, and this in effect leads to a “group” structure. But, contrary to
- Poincaré’s belief in the a priori nature of the group of dis- placements, this
- is developed gradually as the ultimate form of equilibrium reached by this
- motor organisation. Successive co-ordinations (combinativity), reversals
- (reversibility), detours (associativity) and conservations of position
- (identity) gradually give rise to the group, which serves as a necessary
- equilibrium for actions.
-
- At the first two stages (reflexes and elementary habits), we could not even speak
- of a space common to the various per- ceptual modalities, since there are as
- many spaces, all mutually heterogeneous, as there are qualitatively distinct
- fields (mouth, visual, tactile, etc.). It is only in the course of the third
- stage that the mutual assimilation of these various spaces becomes system- atic
- owing to the co-ordination of vision with prehension. Now, step by step with
- these co-ordinations, we see growing up elementary spatial systems which
- already presage the form of composition characteristic of the group. Thus, in
- the case of interrupted circular reaction, the subject returns to the starting-
- point to begin again; when his eyes are following a moving object that is
- travelling too fast for continuous vision (falling etc.), the subject
- occasionally catches up with the object by dis- placements of his own body to
- correct for those of the external moving object.
-
- But it is as well to realise that, if we take the point of view of the subject
- and not merely that of a mathematical observer, the construction of a group
- structure implies at least two conditions: the concept of an object and the
- decentralisation of movements by correcting for, and even reversing, their
- initial egocentricity. In fact, it is clear that the reversibility
- characteristic of the group presupposes the concept of an object, and also vice
- versa, since to retrieve an object is to make it possible for oneself to return
- (by displacing either the object itself or one’s own body). The object is
- simply the constant due to the reversible composition of the group.
- Furthermore, as Poincaré himself has clearly shown, the idea of displacement as
- such implies the possibility of differentiating between irreversible changes of
- state and those changes of position that are characterized precisely by their
- reversibility (or by their possible correction through movements of one’s own
- body). It is obvious, therefore, that without con- servation of objects there
- could not be any “group”, since then everything would appear as a “change of
- state”. The object and the group of displacements are thus indissociable, the
- one con- stituting the static aspect and the other the dynamic aspect of the
- same reality. But this is not all: a world with no objects is a universe with
- no systematic differentiation between subjective and external realities, a world
- that is consequently “adualistic” (J. M. Baldwin). By this very fact, such a
- universe would be centred on one’s own actions, the subject being all the more
- dominated by this egocentric point of view because he remains
- un-self-conscious. But the group implies just the opposite attitude: a complete
- decentralisation, such that one’s own body is located as one element among
- others in a system of displacements enabling one to distinguish between one’s
- own movements and those of objects.
-
- -- 123-125