aboutsummaryrefslogtreecommitdiff
path: root/books/philosophy/stasis-before-the-state.md
blob: 20e09c24a2d097fff3e854b876b4b94cd9c1e0b7 (plain)
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
[[!meta title="Stasis Before the State: Nine Theses on Agonistic Democracy"]]

* Athor: Dimitris Vardoulakis
* References:
  * https://www.worldcat.org/title/stasis-before-the-state-nine-theses-on-agonistic-democracy/oclc/1000452218
  * https://muse.jhu.edu/chapter/2009359
  * https://www.jstor.org/stable/j.ctt1xhr6vd
  * https://www.academia.edu/35908382/Vardoulakis_Stasis_Before_the_State_--_Introduction
  * https://www.fordhampress.com/9780823277414/stasis-before-the-state/

## Excerpts

    This question would be trivial if sovereignty is under­
    stood simply as the sovereignty of specific states. The
    question is pertinent when we consider the vio­lence
    functioning as the structural princi­ple of sovereignty.
    Sovereignty can only persist and the state that it sup­
    ports can only ever reproduce its structures—­political,
    economic, ­legal, and so on—­through recourse to certain
    forms of vio­lence. Such vio­lence is at its most effective
    the less vis­i­ble and hence the less bloody it is. This in­
    sight has been developed brilliantly by thinkers such
    as Gramsci, u
    ­ nder the rubric of hegemony; Althusser,
    through the concept of ideology; and Foucault, as the
    notion of power. It is in this context that we should also
    consider Carl Schmitt’s definition of the po­liti­cal as the
    identification of the e ­ nemy. They all agree on the essen­
    tial or structural vio­lence defining sovereignty—­their
    divergent accounts of that vio­lence notwithstanding.
    The prob­lem of a space outside sovereignty is com­

    [...]

    Posing the question of an outside to sovereignty
    within the context of the mechanism of exclusion turns
    the spotlight to what I call the ruse of sovereignty. This
    essentially consists in the paradox that the assertion of
    a space outside sovereignty is nothing other than the as­
    sertion of an excluded space and consequently signals
    the mobilization of the logic of sovereignty.

    [...]

    To put this in the vocabulary used h
    ­ ere, the at-
    tempt to exclude exclusion is itself exclusory and thus
    reproduces the logic of exclusion.

    [...]

    Turning to Solon’s first demo­cratic constitution,
    I ­will suggest in this book that it is pos­si­ble by identify­
    ing the conflictual nature of democracy—or what the
    ancient Greeks called stasis. Agonistic monism holds
    that stasis is the definitional characteristic of democ­
    racy and of any other pos­si­ble constitutional form. Sta­
    sis or conflict as the basis of all po­liti­cal arrangements
    then becomes another way of saying that democracy is
    the form of e ­ very constitution. Hence, stasis comes be-
    fore any conception of the state that relies on the ruse of
    sovereignty.

    The obvious objection to this position would be about
    the nature of this conflict. Hobbes makes the state of
    nature — which he explic­itly identifies with democracy —­
    also the precondition of the commonwealth. Schmitt
    defines the po­liti­cal as the identification of the enemy.

    [...]
    
    ent power. Is t ­ here a way out of this entangled knot?
    Antonio Negri’s most significant contribution to po­
    liti­cal philosophy is, in my opinion, precisely at this
    juncture. His intervention starts with his book on Spi­
    noza, The Savage Anomaly, in which he distinguishes
    between potentia (constituent power) and potestas (con­
    stituted power). 20 It is most explic­itly treated in Insur-
    gencies, which provides an account of the development
    of constituent power in philosophical texts from early
    modernity onward and examines the function of con­
    stituent power in significant historical events. 21 The
    starting premise of this investigation is the rejection of
    ent power. Is t ­ here a way out of this entangled knot?
    Antonio Negri’s most significant contribution to po­
    liti­cal philosophy is, in my opinion, precisely at this
    juncture. His intervention starts with his book on Spi­
    noza, The Savage Anomaly, in which he distinguishes
    between potentia (constituent power) and potestas (con­
    stituted power). 20 It is most explic­itly treated in Insur-
    gencies, which provides an account of the development
    of constituent power in philosophical texts from early
    modernity onward and examines the function of con­
    stituent power in significant historical events. 21 The
    starting premise of this investigation is the rejection of
    and avoiding the ruse of sovereignty. 23
    The appeal to constituent power gives Negri the means
    to provide an account of democracy as creative activity.
    This has a wide spectrum of aspects and implications
    that I can only gesture t ­ oward ­here. For instance, this
    approach shows how democracy requires a convergence
    of the ontological, the ethical, and the political—­which
    is also a position central to my own proj­ect (see Thesis
    6). Consequently, democracy is not reducible to a con­
    stituted form, and thus Negri can provide a nonrepre­
    sen­ta­tional account of democracy. This is impor­tant
    because it enables Marx’s own distaste for representative
    democracy to resonate with con­temporary sociology
    and po­liti­cal economy—­a proj­ect that starts with Negri’s
    involvement in Italian workerism and culminates in his
    collaborations with Michael Hardt. Besides the details,
    which Negri has been developing for four de­cades, the
    impor­tant point is that this description of democracy
    and constituent power is consistently juxtaposed to the
    po­liti­cal tradition that privileges constituted power and
    sovereignty. 24
    
    There is, however, a significant drawback in Negri’s
    approach. It concerns the lack of a consistent account of
    vio­lence in his work.
    
    [...]
    
    Without a
    consideration of vio­lence, radical democracy ­w ill never
    discover its agonistic aspect, namely, that conflict or
    stasis is the precondition of the po­liti­cal and that, as
    such, all po­liti­cal forms are effects of the demo­cratic. In
    other words, Negri’s obfuscation of the question of vio­
    lence can never lead to agonistic monism.
    
    [...]
    
Production of the real:

    Second, the state of emergency leading to justification
    does not have to be “real”—it simply needs to be credi­
    ble. Truth or falsity are not properties of power—as Fou­
    cault very well recognized—­and the reason for this, I
    would add, is that power’s justifications are rhetorical
    strategies and hence unconcerned with validity. This is
    the point where my account significantly diverges from
    
    [...]
    
    If we are to understand better sovereign vio­lence, we
    need to investigate further the ways in which vio­lence is
    justified. Sovereignty uses justification rhetorically. In­
    stead of being concerned with w
    ­ hether the justifications
    of actions are true or false, sovereignty is concerned
    with ­whether its justifications are believed by ­those it af­
    fects.

    [...]

Torture:

    Greek po­liti­cal philosophy. 4 Hannah Arendt also pays
    par­tic­u­lar attention to this meta­phor. According to Ar­
    endt, Plato needs the meta­phor of the politician as a
    craftsman in order to compensate for the lack of the no­
    tion of authority in Greek thought. ­These Platonic meta­
    phorics include the meta­phor of the statesman as a
    physician who heals an ailing polis. 5 The meta­phor of
    craftsmanship is used as a justification of po­liti­cal power.
    craftsmanship is used as a justification of po­liti­cal power.
    The meta­phor persists in modernity, and we can find
    examples much closer to home. Mao Zedong justifies
    the purges of the Cultural Revolution on the following
    grounds: “Our object in exposing errors and criticizing
    shortcomings is like that of curing a disease. The entire
    purpose is to save the person.” 6 Whoever does not con­
    form to the Maoist ideal is “ill” and needs to be “cured.”
    Similarly, George Papadopoulos, the col­o­nel who headed
    the Greek junta from 1967 to 1974, repeatedly described
    Greece as an ill patient requiring an operation. The dic­
    tatorial regime justified its vio­lence by drawing an anal­
    ogy of its exceptional powers to the powers of the head
    surgeon in a hospital emergency room. Th
    ­ ese operations
    on “patients” took place not in hospitals but in dark po­
    lice cells or in vari­ous forms of prisons or concentration
    camps. And the instruments of the “operations” ­were
    not t ­ hose of the surgeon but rather of the torturer and
    in many cases also of the executioner. The analogy be­
    tween the surgeon and the torturer is mobilized to pro­
    vide reasons for the exercise of vio­lence. An emergency
    mobilizes rhetorical strategies that justify vio­lence, ir­
    respective of the fact that such a justification may be
    completely fabulatory.

    -- 32-33