1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
|
[[!meta title="Stasis Before the State: Nine Theses on Agonistic Democracy"]]
* Athor: Dimitris Vardoulakis
* References:
* https://www.worldcat.org/title/stasis-before-the-state-nine-theses-on-agonistic-democracy/oclc/1000452218
* https://muse.jhu.edu/chapter/2009359
* https://www.jstor.org/stable/j.ctt1xhr6vd
* https://www.academia.edu/35908382/Vardoulakis_Stasis_Before_the_State_--_Introduction
* https://www.fordhampress.com/9780823277414/stasis-before-the-state/
* Topics:
* Ruse of sovereignty.
* Diference between justification and judgement.
## Excerpts
This question would be trivial if sovereignty is under
stood simply as the sovereignty of specific states. The
question is pertinent when we consider the violence
functioning as the structural principle of sovereignty.
Sovereignty can only persist and the state that it sup
ports can only ever reproduce its structures—political,
economic, legal, and so on—through recourse to certain
forms of violence. Such violence is at its most effective
the less visible and hence the less bloody it is. This in
sight has been developed brilliantly by thinkers such
as Gramsci, u
nder the rubric of hegemony; Althusser,
through the concept of ideology; and Foucault, as the
notion of power. It is in this context that we should also
consider Carl Schmitt’s definition of the political as the
identification of the e nemy. They all agree on the essen
tial or structural violence defining sovereignty—their
divergent accounts of that violence notwithstanding.
The problem of a space outside sovereignty is com
[...]
Posing the question of an outside to sovereignty
within the context of the mechanism of exclusion turns
the spotlight to what I call the ruse of sovereignty. This
essentially consists in the paradox that the assertion of
a space outside sovereignty is nothing other than the as
sertion of an excluded space and consequently signals
the mobilization of the logic of sovereignty.
[...]
To put this in the vocabulary used h
ere, the at-
tempt to exclude exclusion is itself exclusory and thus
reproduces the logic of exclusion.
[...]
Turning to Solon’s first democratic constitution,
I will suggest in this book that it is possible by identify
ing the conflictual nature of democracy—or what the
ancient Greeks called stasis. Agonistic monism holds
that stasis is the definitional characteristic of democ
racy and of any other possible constitutional form. Sta
sis or conflict as the basis of all political arrangements
then becomes another way of saying that democracy is
the form of e very constitution. Hence, stasis comes be-
fore any conception of the state that relies on the ruse of
sovereignty.
The obvious objection to this position would be about
the nature of this conflict. Hobbes makes the state of
nature — which he explicitly identifies with democracy —
also the precondition of the commonwealth. Schmitt
defines the political as the identification of the enemy.
[...]
ent power. Is t here a way out of this entangled knot?
Antonio Negri’s most significant contribution to po
litical philosophy is, in my opinion, precisely at this
juncture. His intervention starts with his book on Spi
noza, The Savage Anomaly, in which he distinguishes
between potentia (constituent power) and potestas (con
stituted power). 20 It is most explicitly treated in Insur-
gencies, which provides an account of the development
of constituent power in philosophical texts from early
modernity onward and examines the function of con
stituent power in significant historical events. 21 The
starting premise of this investigation is the rejection of
ent power. Is t here a way out of this entangled knot?
Antonio Negri’s most significant contribution to po
litical philosophy is, in my opinion, precisely at this
juncture. His intervention starts with his book on Spi
noza, The Savage Anomaly, in which he distinguishes
between potentia (constituent power) and potestas (con
stituted power). 20 It is most explicitly treated in Insur-
gencies, which provides an account of the development
of constituent power in philosophical texts from early
modernity onward and examines the function of con
stituent power in significant historical events. 21 The
starting premise of this investigation is the rejection of
and avoiding the ruse of sovereignty. 23
The appeal to constituent power gives Negri the means
to provide an account of democracy as creative activity.
This has a wide spectrum of aspects and implications
that I can only gesture t oward here. For instance, this
approach shows how democracy requires a convergence
of the ontological, the ethical, and the political—which
is also a position central to my own project (see Thesis
6). Consequently, democracy is not reducible to a con
stituted form, and thus Negri can provide a nonrepre
sentational account of democracy. This is important
because it enables Marx’s own distaste for representative
democracy to resonate with contemporary sociology
and political economy—a project that starts with Negri’s
involvement in Italian workerism and culminates in his
collaborations with Michael Hardt. Besides the details,
which Negri has been developing for four decades, the
important point is that this description of democracy
and constituent power is consistently juxtaposed to the
political tradition that privileges constituted power and
sovereignty. 24
There is, however, a significant drawback in Negri’s
approach. It concerns the lack of a consistent account of
violence in his work.
[...]
Without a
consideration of violence, radical democracy w ill never
discover its agonistic aspect, namely, that conflict or
stasis is the precondition of the political and that, as
such, all political forms are effects of the democratic. In
other words, Negri’s obfuscation of the question of vio
lence can never lead to agonistic monism.
Production of the real:
Second, the state of emergency leading to justification
does not have to be “real”—it simply needs to be credi
ble. Truth or falsity are not properties of power—as Fou
cault very well recognized—and the reason for this, I
would add, is that power’s justifications are rhetorical
strategies and hence unconcerned with validity. This is
the point where my account significantly diverges from
[...]
If we are to understand better sovereign violence, we
need to investigate further the ways in which violence is
justified. Sovereignty uses justification rhetorically. In
stead of being concerned with w
hether the justifications
of actions are true or false, sovereignty is concerned
with whether its justifications are believed by those it af
fects.
Torture:
Greek political philosophy. 4 Hannah Arendt also pays
particular attention to this metaphor. According to Ar
endt, Plato needs the metaphor of the politician as a
craftsman in order to compensate for the lack of the no
tion of authority in Greek thought. These Platonic meta
phorics include the metaphor of the statesman as a
physician who heals an ailing polis. 5 The metaphor of
craftsmanship is used as a justification of political power.
craftsmanship is used as a justification of political power.
The metaphor persists in modernity, and we can find
examples much closer to home. Mao Zedong justifies
the purges of the Cultural Revolution on the following
grounds: “Our object in exposing errors and criticizing
shortcomings is like that of curing a disease. The entire
purpose is to save the person.” 6 Whoever does not con
form to the Maoist ideal is “ill” and needs to be “cured.”
Similarly, George Papadopoulos, the colonel who headed
the Greek junta from 1967 to 1974, repeatedly described
Greece as an ill patient requiring an operation. The dic
tatorial regime justified its violence by drawing an anal
ogy of its exceptional powers to the powers of the head
surgeon in a hospital emergency room. Th
ese operations
on “patients” took place not in hospitals but in dark po
lice cells or in various forms of prisons or concentration
camps. And the instruments of the “operations” were
not t hose of the surgeon but rather of the torturer and
in many cases also of the executioner. The analogy be
tween the surgeon and the torturer is mobilized to pro
vide reasons for the exercise of violence. An emergency
mobilizes rhetorical strategies that justify violence, ir
respective of the fact that such a justification may be
completely fabulatory.
-- 32-33
Razão instrumental:
Let us return to consider more carefully how sover
eign violence always strives for justification. This means
that we can characterize the acts of sovereignty as con
forming to a rationalized instrumentalism. Sovereign
violence is instrumental in the sense that it always aims
toward something—it is not vio
lence for vio
lence’s
sake. This means that the desired outcome of sover
eign violence is calculated with the help of reason. The
extrapolation of violence in instrumental terms is noth
ing new. For instance, Hannah Arendt presents instru
mentalism as the defining feature of violence. 7 Yet the
instrumentalism of sovereign violence is not as self-
evident as it may at first appear. For instance, as Fran
çois Jullien shows, the conception of an instrumental
thinking as appropriate to the political arises in ancient
Greece, and it does not characterize the Chinese cul
ture, including even the ways in which warfare is con
ceived. 8 The important point, then, is to remember that
the instrumentality of reason in the serv ice of a justifi
cation of violence is a characteristic of sovereignty as it
is developed in the Western political and philosophical
tradition.
The “invention” of the instrumentality of reason is
an important moment in the history of thought, and
its “inventors,” the ancient Greeks, amply recognized its
importance. In fact, their tragedies are concerned pre
cisely with the clash between the older forms of thinking
and new forms exemplified by instrumental reason. The
best example of this is perhaps the Oresteia. In the first
play of the trilogy, Agamemnon is murdered by his wife,
Clytemnestra. In the second play, Orestes, Agamem
non’s son, responds by killing his mother. In the third
play, the Eumenides, the court of Athens is called to de
cide w
hether Orestes’s murder was justified. The alter
natives are that he is e ither guilty of matricide pure and
simple or that his act was a political one aiming to free
Argos of a tyrant. Th
ere is, then, a standstill or stasis—
and I draw again attention to this word, to which I w
ill
return later—between the two different l egal frame
works: one legality privileging kinship, the other privi
leging instrumental rationality whereby the murder of
Clytemnestra is justified by the end of saving the city
from a tyrant. The judges’ vote is a tie, at which point
the goddess Athena, who presides over the proceedings,
casts the vote to f ree Orestes of the charge of matricide.
Calculative reason prevails as the mode of the political.
But at the same time, it should not be forgotten that the
vote was equally split. For the ancient Athenians, it is
impossible to reconcile the two different legalities—the
politics of kinship and the politics of instrumental
reason. Justice persists in this irreconcilability, despite
its tragic consequences.
-- 33-35
Soberania como persuasão e interpretação:
In other words, the absoluteness of
sovereignty has nothing to do with the power of sover
eignty as it is exercised through its institutions—the
police, the army, the judiciary, and so on. Rather, the
absoluteness of sovereignty is an expression of the rhe
torical and logical mechanisms whereby sovereignty
uses the justification of violence to dominate public de
bate and to persuade the citizens. The exercise of sover
eignty is the effect of an interpretative process. Differently
put, this entails that the justification of violence is more
primary than the legitimate forms assumed by constituded power.
Without an effective justification, any government loses its
mandate to govern, even though its
decisions and political actions, its policies, and its legis
lative agenda may perfectly conform to the law of the
state.
-- 52-53
Democracia:
How can democracy as the other of sovereignty be
mobilized to respond to sovereignty’s justification of
violence? This final question is, I believe, the most fun
damental political question. It essentially asks about
the relation of sovereignty and democracy. What is re
quired at this juncture in order to broach the relation
between democracy and sovereignty further is a better
determination of democracy.
-- 53
> The first ever democracy was instituted through the Solonian reforms that were
> introduced to counteract a chronical political no less than social crisis in
> Athens. The crisis was the result of a protracted animosity between the rich
> and the poor parties. The confrontation was largely because of material
> inequalities, such as the requirement to hold property in order to be a
> citizen, and the economic inequalities that were threatening to turn into
> slaves a large portion of the poor population who had defaulted on their
> payments. Unsurprisingly, given the sensitivity of these issues, tensions
> ran high, and the city often found itself in conflict or stasis, with the two
> sides taking arms against each other. The situation had reached an acute
> crisis, at which point the Athenians re solved that they had to take decisive
> action. They turned to Solon, who was largely viewed as impartial and wise, to
> write a new constitution for the city. He responded by compiling the first ever
> democratic constitution.
>
> [...]
>
> The crisis is the condition of citizenship and residency within
> Athens and even of the possibility of the operation of the state. Solon's law
> does not describe measures whereby the crisis can be avoided. Instead, it
> describes how everyone is required to participate in it -- as if the aim is to
> accentuate the crisis. Those who avoid conflict will be punished. The
> democratic overcoming of crisis consists in the institutionalization of
> crisis within the constitution. According to Solon, his fellow Athenians need
> to recognize the illusion that the implementation of measures can always
> prevent crisis. According to Solon, democracy consists in the dispelling of
> that illusion. This does not mean that certain measures or policies cannot and
> should not be devised to ameliorate or evade predictable crises. Rather, it
> highlights that such measures are never adequate. Or, to put it the other
> way around, Solon sees crisis as a way of being, as a condition of existence,
> and he is determined that his democratic constitution aknowledges this.
>
> -- 57-58
> Democracy does not seek to be charitable to the other but instead affords the
> other the respect to give them a voice to express their opinions as well as to
> debate and rebuke these opinions.
>
> -- 73
> These insights amount to saying that a democratic being is conflictual
> -- which is to say that it cannot find certainty in any political regime
> promising unity or in a state characterized by order, peace, and stability.
> Rather, democracy in this sense is a regime that is inherently open to the
> possibility of conflict without any underlying structure to regulate this
> conflict or to resolve it to some thing posited as higher.
>
> -- 76
|