[[!meta title="Torture and Truth"]] * [Torture and Truth](https://www.worldcat.org/title/torture-and-truth/oclc/20823386). * By Page duBois. ## About First published in 1991, this book — through the examination of ancient Greek literary, philosophical and legal texts — analyses how the Athenian torture of slaves emerged from and reinforced the concept of truth as something hidden in the human body. It discusses the tradition of understanding truth as something that is generally concealed and the ideas of ‘secret space’ in both the female body and the Greek temple. This philosophy and practice is related to Greek views of the ‘Other’ (women and outsiders) and considers the role of torture in distinguishing slave and free in ancient Athens. A wide range of perspectives — from Plato to Sartre — are employed to examine the subject. ## Topics * Example of actual tortures that took place: see defense of Andokides. Footnote 6. ## Excerpts ### Machine atroci Inside sat other devices. The iron maiden of Frankfurt, a larger-than-life-size female body, cast in iron, strangely reminiscent of one of those Russian dolls, a rounded maternal peasant body that opens horizontally to reveal another identical doll inside, that opens again and again until one reaches a baby, perhaps, I can’t recall, in its deepest inside. This body, propped open, had been cast with a vertical split, its interior consisting of two sets of sharp iron spikes that, when the maiden was closed on a captive human body, penetrated that body, trapping it upright as it killed in a grotesque parody of pregnancy made a coffin. [...] For me, the pear was not the most compelling “machine” on display. There sat, on one of the tables inside the Quirinale Palace, a simple modern device, looking something like a microphone, with electrodes dangling from it. The catalogue acknowledged that critics had objected to the inclusion of this instrument in the exhibit. [...] As I recognized what it must be, pieced together an idea of its functions from recently read accounts of refugees from the Argentinian junta and from Central America, recalled films of the Algerian war, news stories of the reign of the colonels in Greece, this instrument composed of the only too familiar elements of modern technology defamiliarized the devices on exhibit; removing them from the universe of the museum, it identified them with the calculated infliction of human agony. It recontextualized all the other objects, prevented them from being an aesthetic series, snatched them from the realm of the commodified antique, recalled suffering. The ancient Greeks and Romans routinely tortured slaves as part of their legal systems. So what? Is the recollection of this fact merely a curiosity, a memory of the “antique” which allows us to marvel at our progress from the past of Western culture, our abolition of slavery? Some of us congratulate ourselves on our evolution from a barbaric pagan past, from the world of slave galleys and crucifixions, of vomitoria and gladiatorial contests, of pederasty and polytheism. But there is another, supplementary or contestatory narrative told about ancient Greek culture—a narrative about the noble origins of Western civilization. This narrative has analogies with the Quirinale exhibit—it represents the past as a set of detached objects, redolent with antique atmosphere. This alternate and prejudicially selective gaze at the high culture of antiquity, the achievement of those ancient Greeks and Romans to whom we point when we discuss our golden age, produces an ideological text for the whole world now, mythologies about democracy versus communist totalitarianism, about progress, civilized values, human rights. Because we are descended from this noble ancient culture, from the inventors of philosophy and democracy, we see ourselves as privileged, as nobly obliged to guide the whole benighted world toward Western culture’s version of democracy and enlightenment. But even as we gaze at high culture, at its origins in antiquity, at its present manifestations in the developed nations, the “base” practices of torturers throughout the world, many of them trained by North Americans, support this narrative by forcing it on others, by making it the hegemonic discourse about history. So-called high culture—philosophical, forensic, civic discourses and practices—is of a piece from the very beginning, from classical antiquity, with the deliberate infliction of human suffering. It is my argument in this book that more is at stake in our recognition of this history than antiquarianism, than complacency about our advances from barbarism to civilization. That truth is unitary, that truth may finally be extracted by torture, is part of our legacy from the Greeks and, therefore, part of our idea of “truth.” ### Sartre "Torture is senseless violence, born in fear. The purpose of it is to force from one tongue, amid its screams and its vomiting up of blood, the secret of everything. Senseless violence: whether the victim talks or whether he dies under his agony, the secret that he cannot tell is always somewhere else and out of reach. It is the executioner who becomes Sisyphus. If he puts the question at all, he will have to continue forever." ### Tradition, secrets, truth and torture The Gestapo taught the French, who taught the Americans in Indo-China, and they passed on some of their expertise to the Argentinian, Chilean, El Salvadoran torturers. But this essay is not meant to be a genealogy of modern torture. Rather I am concerned with what Sartre calls “the secret of everything” with the relationship between torture and the truth, which “is always somewhere else and out of reach.” A crucial point (an "crucial" also in the sense of the crucified, tortured body): I want to show how the logic of our philosophical tradition, of some of our inherited beliefs about truth, leads almost inevitably to conceiving of the body of the other as the site from which truth can be produced, and to using violence if necessary to extract that truth. [...] I want to work out how the Greek philosophical idea of truth was produced in history and what role the social practice of judicial torture played in its production. I don’t want to suggest that the ancient Greeks invented torture, or that it belongs exclusively to the Western philosophical tradition, or that abhorrence of torture is not also part of that tradition. But I also refuse to adopt the moral stance of those who pretend that torture is the work of “others,” that it belongs to the third world, that we can condemn it from afar. To stand thus is to eradicate history, to participate both in the exportation of torture as a product of Western civilization, and in the concealment of its ancient and perhaps necessary coexistence with much that we hold dear. The very idea of truth we receive from the Greeks, those ancestors whom Allan Bloom names for us,3 is inextricably linked with the practice of torture, which has almost always been the ultimate attempt to discover a secret “always out of reach.” [...] The ancient Greek word for torture is basanos. It means first of all the touchstone used to test gold for purity; the Greeks extended its meaning to denote a test or trial to determine whether something or someone is real or genuine. It then comes to mean also inquiry by torture, “the question,” torture.4 In the following pages I will discuss the semantic field of the word basanos, its uses in various contexts, both literal and metaphorical. [...] This analysis will lead me to consideration of the idea of truth as secret in ancient Greek thought, in literary, ritual, and philosophical practices [...] The desire for a reliable test to determine the fidelity of a suspect intimate recurs in Greek poetry, and later poets often employ the metaphor of the testing of metal to describe the necessity and unreliability of testing for the fidelity of friends. The Lydians of Asia Minor had invented the use of metal currency, of money, in the seventh century B.C.E. The polis or city-state of Aegina was reputed to be the first Greek city to establish a silver coinage; in the classical period several different coinages circulated. By the fifth century B.C.E. coins of small enough denominations existed to enter into the economic transactions of daily life. In Euripides’ Hippolytus the Athenian king Theseus, bewildered by contradictory accounts of an alleged seduction attempt by his son against his wife, uses monetary language to convey his confusion about the mysteries of domestic intimacy: [...] Theseus employs the language of the banker, of the money-lender, to suggest that one of his friends, that is, of those dear to him, either his son or his wife, is false and counterfeit. [...] pollution is a religious term, connected with the impurity of blood shed, of unclean sacrificial practices or murder.10 In the archaic period, the state of freedom from pollution is sometimes connected with notions of inherited purity, of uncontaminated descent from the generations of heroes, from the gods, ideas of inherited excellence through which the aristocrats justified their dominance in the archaic cities. ### Governing, the steering of a ship in the hands of the aristocracy The very last lines of the poem echo the concerns of Theognis, a recognition of the political disturbances of the ancient city, and the desire of the aristocratic poet for a steady hand, sanctioned by blood and tradition, at the city’s helm: Let us praise his brave brothers too, because they bear on high the ways of Thessaly and bring them glory. In their hands belongs the piloting of cities, their fathers’ heritage. (68-72) [poet Pindar, in Pythian 10] This last phrase might be rendered: “in the care of the good men [Theognis’s agathoi, a political term] lie the inherited, paternal pilotings, governings [following the metaphor of the ship of state] of cities.” The city is a ship that must be guided by those who are capable by birth of piloting it, that is to say, the agathoi, the good, the aristocrats. The basanos reveals the good, separates base metal from pure gold, aristocrat from commoner. ### A change of meaning The Sophoclean language, and its ambiguity, reveal the gradual transition of the meaning of the word basanos from “test” to “torture.” The literal meaning, “touchstone,” gives way to a figurative meaning, “test,” then over time changes to “torture,” as the analogy is extended to the testing of human bodies in juridical procedures for the Athenian courts. Is the history of basanos itself in ancient Athens a process of refiguration, the alienation of the test from a metal to the slave, the other? Such a transfer is literally catachresis, the improper use of words, the application of a term to a thing which it does not properly denote, abuse or perversion of a trope or metaphor (OED); George Puttenham, the Elizabethan rhetorician, calls catachresis “the figure of abuse.” The modern English word touchstone is similarly employed by people who have no idea of the archaic reference to the lapis Lydius, also called in English basanite . The figurative use of the word touchstone has taken the place of the literal meaning. [...] The forensic language of Oedipus Rex fuses heroic legend with the poetic representation of the city’s institutions. The mythic narrative of Oedipus’s encounter with the Sphinx, set in the most remote past, and the struggle between Kreon and Oedipus over the investigation of an ancient and mythic homicide, here meet the daily life of the democratic polis. The language of Sophokles’ tragedy might be said to exemplify not only the contradictions between the tyranny of the fictional past and the “secret ballots,” alluded to disparagingly by Pindar, of the audience’s present, but also to represent dramatically, in an almost Utopian manner, a synthesis of the Greeks’ legendary origins and their political processes. The chorus’s attempt to judge Oedipus resembles the aristocratic reveler’s testing of his fellow symposiasts, using as it does archaic, lyric language; it is also like the democratic jury’s testing of a citizen on trial, alluding obliquely at the same time to the juridical torture of slaves in the Athenian legal system, a process which by this time was referred to as the basanos. Some of the semantic processes that transformed basanos as touchstone into the term for legal torture can be seen in the use of the term in the Oedipus Coloneus. This tragedy is only obliquely concerned with the process of democracy, with the new institutions of the mid-fifth century which mediated between the city’s aristocratic past and its democratic present. It speaks instead of the exhaustion of the political, of disillusionment with parties and with war, of metaphysical solutions to problems too bitter to be resolved in mortal agones. [...] The basanos, no longer an autonomous, inert, inanimate tool for assaying metal, has become a struggle between two forces, a contest that assumes physical violence, a reconcretizing of the “touchstone,” which is neither the literal stone nor a metaphorical ordeal. Hands, pitted one against the other, rematerialize the test. The touchstone sets stone against metal; the test of friends sets one against another; here the agon, the contest implicit in the notion of basanos, takes on a new connotation, one of combat between enemies. Some historians of the ancient city believe that the word basanos refers not to physical torture, but to a legal interrogation that does not involve violence. Others claim that the threat of torture may have been present in the word, but that there is no evidence that torture was actually ever practiced.16 It seems to me very unlikely , even though the ancient evidence does not describe directly any single case of torture, that the frequent mentions of basanos in contexts of physical intimidation can refer to anything but the practice of torture. The accidents of survival of ancient material may mean that we have no single documented instance of torture having been applied, but the many uses of the term, not only in the context of the law court, suggest a cultural acceptance of the meaning “torture” for basanos, and an assumption that torture occurred. For example, the historian Herodotos, in recounting an incident that took place during the Persian Wars, in the early years of the fifth century B.C.E., describes the Athenian hero Themistokles’ secret negotiations with the Persian emperor Xerxes after the battle of Salamis: Themistocles lost no time in getting a message through to Xerxes. The men he chose for this purpose were all people he could trust to keep his instructions secret [sigan], even under torture [es pasan basanon]. [...] This passage suggests not only that basanos was not merely interrogation, but that with the meaning torture it formed part of the vocabulary of daily life, and that torture figured in the relations between ancient states as well as in the legal processes of the democratic city. Themistokles had to take into account the ability of his emissaries to resist physical torture, pasan basanon, “any, all torture,” when deciding whom to send to the Persian emperor. He required silence under extreme interrogation, since he was claiming falsely to have protected Xerxes from the pursuit of the Greeks after the Persians’ defeat. And Herodotos uses the word basanos as if the meaning “torture” were common currency. As do Sophokles’ Oedipus plays, Herodotos’s text offers a double vision, providing further evidence about the place of torture in the democracy and in its prehis-tory. Sophokles writes from within the democracy about episodes from the archaic, legendary past of the city. Herodotos writes from the world of the mid-fifth century, the time of Sophokles and the great imperial age of Athens, looking back half a century. The victories of Athens in the Persian Wars had enabled and produced the great flowering of Athenian culture and ambition in the middle of the fifth century. Herodotos’s retrospective gaze at the origins of the democracy and its empire paints the portrait of Themistokles, one of the great aristocrats whose power and vision shaped the evolution of the democratic city. His encouragement, for example, of the policy of spending the city’s mining wealth on its fleet, rather than distributing of monies to the citizens, meant that the poorest citizens in Athens, who manned the fleet, participated actively and powerfully in the political and military decisions of the following years. In the incident Herodotos describes, Themistokles takes care to ensure that his self-interested machinations not be known by the Athenians he led. Themistokles, like Oedipus, has become a creature of legend. [...] Silence under torture may be coded as an aristocratic virtue. [...] it indicates the degree to which silence under pain is ideologically associated with nobility. The slave has no resources through which to resist submitting to pain and telling all. In contrast the aristocratic soldier, noble by both birth and training, maintains laconic silence in the face of physical abuse. ### Comedy and inversion We find a comic parody of the use of basanos for the courtroom in Aristophanes’ Frogs.20 The comedy is devoted to themes of judgment, discrimination, and evaluation . Dionysos and his slave Xanthias have set off on a journey to Hades to retrieve the tragic poet Euripides, but end by choosing Aeschylus to bring back with them, claiming him over Euripides as the superior poet. Dionysos had dressed for the trip as Herakles, who had once successfully entered and, more importantly, departed the realm of the dead, but when he learns that Herakles is persona non grata in Hades, he forces his slave to trade costumes with him. When Xanthias is mistaken for Herakles and about to be arrested as a dog-napper, for the stealing of Kerberos, the slave offers to give up his own supposed slave, really the god Dionysos, to torture [...] The result is a beating contest in which Xanthias seems sure to win, accustomed as he, a real slave, is to such beatings. The beatings constitute not punishment but torture, and the language of the comedy reflects this fact. The torture will reveal the truth, show which of the two is a god, which a slave. The comedy works on the reversal of slave and god; Xanthias claims a god would not be hurt by a beating, but the slave, the lowest of mortal beings, might in fact be thought, because of experience, most easily to endure a whipping. Dionysos begins to weep under the beating, but claims it’s due to onions. Aiakos is finally unable to decide which of the two is divine. In the parabasis, the address to the audience, that follows, the theme of noble and base currency emerges once again, as if connected by free association with this scene of torture, of the basanos or touchstone. The chorus appeals to the Athenian populace, complaining that Athenians who had committed one fault in a battle at sea were to be put to death, while slaves who had fought alongside their masters had been given their freedom. This seems to the chorus to be a perversion of traditional hierarchical thinking: [...] The comic beating is quite hilarious, of course. But it does not put into question the reality of torture. The exchange has a carnival quality, Dionysos masquerading as slave, slave masquerading as Dionysos masquerading as Herakles, the god beaten like a common slave. The slave remains uppity and insolent, the god cowardly and ridiculous. Comedy permits this representation of the quotidian reality of the polis, the exposure of what cannot be alluded to directly in tragedy, the violence and domination implicit in the situation of bondage. Comedy allows the fictional depiction of the unspeakable, the representation of the lowly slave, the allusion to ordinary cruelty, a commentary on the difficulty of perceiving the essential difference between divine and enslaved beings. [...] If Aristophanes is so iconoclastic as to mock the gods, and to treat the slave as if he were a human character, he does not go so far as to question the institution of the basanos. ### Testing The slave on the rack waits like the metal, pure or alloyed, to be tested. [...] The test assumes that its result will be truth; [...] The truth is generated by torture from the speech of the slave; the sounds of the slave on the rack must by definition contain truth, which the torture produces. And when set against other testimony in a court case, that necessary truth, like a touchstone itself, will show up the truth or falsity of the testimony. The process of testing has been spun out from the simple metallurgist’s experiment, to a new figuration of the work of interrogating matter. It is the slave’s body, not metal, which receives the test; but how can that body be demonstrated to be true or false, pure or alloyed, loyal or disloyal? The basanos assumes first that the slave always lies, then that torture makes him or her always tell the truth, then that the truth produced through torture will always expose the truth or falsehood of the free man’s evidence. ### Athenian democracy and torture Yet the Athenian democracy was at best a sort of oligarchy, one that denied legal and political rights to all women, even daughters of citizens, and to foreigners and slaves residing in Attica. The practice of slave torture is consistent with the democracy’s policies of exclusion, scapegoating, ostracism, and physical cruelty and violence; to overlook or justify torture is to misrecognize and idealize the Athenian state. MacDowell describes the place of torture in the Athenian legal system: A special rule governed the testimony of slaves: they could not appear in court, but a statement which a slave, male or female, had made under torture (basanos) could be produced in court as evidence.3 The party in a trial who wished a slave to be tortured would put his questions in writing, specifying which slaves he wished to have tortured and the questions they were to be asked, and also agreeing to pay the slave’s owner for any permanent damage inflicted on the slave. Athenian citizens could not be tortured. MacDowell reasons as follows about the rule that slave’s testimony could be received in the courtroom only if the slave had been tortured: The reason for this rule must have been that a slave who knew anything material would frequently belong to one of the litigants, and so would be afraid to say anything contrary to his owner’s interests, unless the pressure put on him to reveal the truth was even greater than the punishment for revealing it which he could expect from his master.4 A. R. W. Harrison believes that the right to testify freely in court may have been seen as a privilege, perhaps because witnesses who appeared in court were once thought of as “compurgators,” witnesses who swore to the credibility of a party in a law suit. “Torture must therefore be applied to the slave as a mark of the fact that he was not in himself a free agent entitled to support one side or the other.”5 Since the slave was a valuable piece of property, liable to damage from torture, she or he could not be tortured without permission of the owner.6 If that permission were denied, the opponent often claimed that the evidence which would have been obtained under torture would of certainty have been damning to the slave’s owner. ### Slavery and freedom Jean-Paul Sartre’s [...] says: “Algeria cannot contain two human species, but requires a choice between them”.1 The soldiers who practiced torture on Algerian revolutionaries attempted to reduce their opponents to pure materiality, to the status of animals. [...] Free men and women could be enslaved at any time, although in Athens the Solonian reforms of the sixth century B.C.E. [...] In the Politics Aristotle claims that some people are slaves “by nature” [...] The discourse on the use of torture in ancient Athenian law forms part of an attempt to manage the opposition between slave and free, and it betrays both need and anxiety: need to have a clear boundary between servile and free, anxiety about the impossibility of maintaining this difference. ### Tendency of suspend democracy protections (coup) during crisis [The] incident of the mutilation of the herms shook the stability of the Athenian state, but also points to the future tendencies among the aristocratic and oligarchic parties to suspend democratic protections in a moment of crisis. The logical tendency would seem to be either to extend torture to all who could give evidence, or to forbid torture of any human being. The instability of the distinctions between slave and free, citizen and noncitizen, Greek and foreigner, becomes apparent in these debates on the possibility of state torture of citizens. Athenian citizens treasured the freedom from torture as a privilege of their elevated status; Peisander’s eagerness to abrogate this right is a premonition of the violence and illegality of the oligarchic coup of 411 and of the bloody rule of the Thirty after the defeat of the Athenians by the Spartans in 404.5 ### Truth-making and the secret of everything Another kind of truth, what Sartre calls “the secret of everything,” is named by many Greek writers as the explicit aim of judicial torture. [,,,] In the Greek legal system, the torture of slaves figured as a guarantor of truth, as a process of truth-making. ### Secret ballots and lawyers Jurors received pay for their service in the courts [...] A case was required to be completed within a day at most; several private cases would be tried within a single day. The time alloted for arguments by the opponents in a trial was measured by a water-clock; the amount of water allowed for each side was determined by the seriousness of the charges. After each of the litigants spoke, brought forward witnesses, and had evidence read, the jurors placed disks or pebbles into urns to determine the winner of the suit. [...] At the end of the fifth century it became customary to employ professional writers to compose one’s speech for the court. Thus the scene in the court resembled the great assemblies of the democratic city, with up to six thousand men adjudicating disputes. [...] In this context, the evidence from the torture of slaves is evidence from elsewhere, from another place, another body. It is evidence from outside the community of citizens, of free men. Produced by the basanistês, the torturer, or by the litigant in another scene, at the time of torture, such evidence differs radically from the testimony of free witnesses in the court. It is temporally estranged, institutionally, conventionally marked as evidence of another order; what is curious is that speakers again and again privilege it as belonging to a higher order of truth than that evidence freely offered in the presence of the jurors by present witnesses. [...] There are many such passages. The slave body has become, in the democratic city, the site of torture and of the production of truth. The argument concerning the greater value of slave evidence frequently occurs in accusations against an opponent who has refused to allow his slaves to be tortured. The speaker claims then that this failure to produce slave witnesses proves indirectly that their testimony would condemn their owner. ### Slaves are bodies; citizens possess logos Lykourgos argues against Leokrates [...]: Every one of you knows that in matters of dispute it is considered by far the just and most democratic [dêmotikôtatori] course, when there are male or female slaves, who possess the necessary information, to examine these by torture and so have facts to go upon instead of hearsay, particularly when the case concerns the public and is of vital interest to the state. He argues that by nature the tortured slaves would have told the truth; does this mean that any human being, when tortured, will produce the truth, or that it is the nature of slaves to tell the truth under torture? Free citizen men will be deceived by clever arguments; slaves by nature will not be misled because they think with their bodies. Slaves are bodies; citizens possess logos, reason. [...] This appeal to the practice of torture as an integral and valued part of the legal machinery of the democracy points up the contradictory nature of Athenian democracy, and the ways in which the application of the democratic reforms of Athens were carefully limited to the lives of male citizens, and intrinsic to the production and justification of this notion of male citizenship. ### Notions of truth and the real of the untorturable, the dead In another speech attributed to Antiphon, this one part of a case presumably actually tried, torture again plays an important role in the defense of a man accused of murder, Euxitheos [...] Probably both of these considerations induced him to make the false charges against me which he did; he hoped to gain his freedom, and his one immediate wish was to end the torture. I need not remind you, I think, that witnesses under torture are biased in favour of those who do most of the torturing; they will say anything likely to gratify them. It is their one chance of salvation, especially when the victims of their lies happen not to be present. Had I myself proceeded to give orders that the slave should be racked [strebloun] for not telling the truth, that step in itself would doubtless have been enough to make him stop incriminating me falsely. (5.31-32) The speaker, because for once forced to confront the evidence of a tortured slave, rather than bemoaning the lack of slave evidence, here points out the absolute unreliability of slave evidence, based as it is on the will of the torturer. Bizarrely, however, he ends by claiming that the true truth would have emerged, another truth truer than the first, if he himself had been the torturer. If so, it is interesting that the defendant distinguishes between an essentialist notion of truth and a pragmatic notion of truth in the case of the slave, but not in the case of the free foreigner, where a reversion to the essentialist notion appears to occur. And the logic he exposes, that the slave will say anything to gratify his torturer, is dropped as soon as he himself becomes the torturer. We can imagine the body of the slave ripped apart in a tug-of-war between two litigants, in a law case in which he was implicated only by proximity. This very slave, who had been purchased by the prosecution, in fact later changed his testimony, according to the speaker because he recognized his imminent doom. Nonetheless the prosecution put him to death. The defendant continues: Clearly, it was not his person, but his evidence, which they required; had the man remained alive, he would have been tortured by me in the same way, and the prosecution would be confronted with their plot: but once he was dead, not only did the loss of his person mean that I was deprived of my opportunity of establishing the truth, but his false statements are assumed to be true. (5.35) All of the prosecution’s case rests on the testimony of the tortured and now dead slave; the defendant claims to be completely frustrated, since now the truth lies in a realm inaccessible to him. He cannot torture the dead man and discover the “real” truth. Even though the slave had at first insisted on the defendant’s innocence, he had under torture called him guilty: At the start, before being placed on the wheel [trokhon], in fact, until extreme pressure was brought to bear, the man adhered to the truth [alêtheia] and declared me innocent. It was only when on the wheel, and when driven to it, that he falsely incriminated me, in order to put an end to the torture. (5.40-41) The persistence of the defendant’s desire himself to torture this slave claims our attention; even after the inevitability of false testimony under torture stands exposed, he bemoans the retreat of the slave into the realm of the untorturable, of the dead. I repeat, let no one cause you to forget that the prosecution put the informer to death, that they used every effort to prevent his appearance in court and to make it impossible for me to take him and examine him under torture on my return.… Instead, they bought the slave and put him to death, entirely on their own initiative [idia], (5.46-47) ### Reasoning attributed to a free man, but foreigner The free man knew that the torture would end; he also could not be bribed by promises of freedom for giving the answers the torturers desired to hear. In this case, the defendant gives priority to the free man’s unfree testimony; unlike the free testimony of an Athenian in a courtroom, this evidence was derived from torture, but the defendant seeks to give it the added authority of the free man in spite of its origin in this procedure tainted with unfreedom, because it supports his view of the case. ### Truth even if it cost lives You do not need to be reminded, gentlemen, that the one occasion when compulsion [anagkai] is as absolute and as effective as is humanly possible, and when the rights of a case are ascertained thereby most surely and most certainly, arises when there is an abundance of witnesses, both slave and free, and it is possible to put pressure [anagkazein] upon the free men by exacting an oath or word of honour, the most solemn and the most awful form of compulsion known to free men, and upon the slaves by other devices [heterais anagkais], which will force them to tell the truth even if their revelations are bound to cost them their lives, as the compulsion of the moment [he gar parousa anagkê] has a stronger influence over each than the fate which he will suffer by compulsion afterwards. (6.25) That is, the free man is compelled by oaths; he might lose his rights as a citizen if he lied under oath. The slave, even though he will certainly be put to death as a consequence of what he reveals under torture, will nonetheless, under torture, reveal the truth. The two kinds of compulsion are equated, one appropriate for the free man, one for the slave. ### Torturability Torture serves not only to exact a truth, some truth or other, which will benefit one side of the case or the other. It also functions as a gambit in the exchange between defendant and prosecution; if for any reason one of them refuses to give up slaves to torture, the other can claim that the missing testimony would of a certainty support his view of things. And as I argued earlier, torture also serves to mark the boundary between slave and free beings. Torture can be enacted against free, non-Greek beings as well as slaves; all “barbarians” are assimilated to slaves. Slaves are barbarians, barbarians are slaves; all are susceptible to torture. Torturability creates a difference which is naturalized. And even the sophistry of the First Tetralogy, which wants to create a category of virtually free in the case of the slave who would have been freed had he lived, seeks to support this division of human beings into free, truth-telling creatures, and torturable slave/barbarians, who will only produce truth on the wheel. ### The Slave's Truth Torture performs at least two functions in the Athenian state. As an instrument of demarcation, it delineates the boundary between slave and free, between the untouchable bodies of free citizens and the torturable bodies of slaves. The ambiguity of slave status, the difficulty of sustaining an absolute sense of differences, is addressed through this practice of the state, which carves the line between slave and free on the bodies of the unfree. In the work of the wheel, the rack, and the whip, the torturer carries out the work of the polis; citizen is made distinct from noncitizen, Greek from barbarian, slave from free. The practice of basanos administers to the anxiety about enslavement, hauntingly evoked in the texts of Athenian tragedy that recall the fall of cities, particularly the fall of Troy, evoked as well in the histories that recount Athenian destruction of subject allies. [...] But the desire to clarify the respective status of slave and free is not the motive, never the explicit motive, of torture. Rather, again and again, even in the face of arguments discounting evidence derived from torture, speakers in the courts describe the basanos as a search for truth. How is this possible? And how are the two desires related? The claim is made that truth resides in the slave body. [...] That is, the master possesses reason, logos. When giving evidence in court, he knows the difference between truth and falsehood, he can reason and produce true speech, logos, and he can reason about the consequences of falsehood , the deprivation of his rights as a citizen. The slave, on the other hand, possessing not reason, but rather a body strong for service (iskhura pros ten anagkaian khrêsin), must be forced to utter the truth, which he can apprehend, although not possessing reason as such. Unlike an animal, a being that possesses only feelings, and therefore can neither apprehend reason, logos, nor speak, legein, the slave can testify when his body is tortured because he recognizes reason without possessing it himself. [...] Thus, according to Aristotle’s logic, representative or not, the slave’s truth is the master’s truth; it is in the body of the slave that the master’s truth lies, and it is in torture that his truth is revealed. The torturer reaches through the master to the slave’s body, and extracts the truth from it. The master can conceal the truth, since he possesses reason and can choose between truth and lie, can choose the penalty associated with false testimony. His own point of vulnerability is the body of his slave, which can be compelled not to lie, can be forced to produce the truth. If he decides to deny the body of his slave to the torturer, assumptions Will be made that condemn him. [...] Aristotle advocates the pragmatic approach; one can argue either side concerning the truth of torture. [...] As Gernet says, “Proof is institutional.” Proof, and therefore truth, are constituted by the Greeks as best found in the evidence derived from torture. Truth, alêtheia, comes from elsewhere, from another place, from the place of the other. ### Torture and Writing The tortured body retains scars, marks that recall the violence inflicted upon it by the torturer. In part because slaves were often tattooed in the ancient world, such marks of torture resonate in the Greek mind with tattoos, and with other forms of metaphorical inscription, in Greek thinking considered analogous to writing on the body.1 I have discussed the topos of corporeal inscription elsewhere. The woman’s body was in ancient Greece sometimes likened to a writing tablet, a surface to be ”ploughed,” inscribed by the hand, the plough, the penis of her husband and master.2 The famous case of the tatooed head: One especially intriguing mention of slave tattooing occurs in Herodotos’s Histories, in a narrative in which the possibility of torture remains implicit. Although I have discussed this episode elsewhere, I want here to draw out its implications for a consideration of the relationship between torture and truth. Histiaios of Miletus sends a message urging revolt to a distant ally by shaving the head of his most trusted slave, tattooing the message on the slave’s head, then waiting for the slave’s hair to grow back. He sends the slave on his journey, ordering him to say at the journey’s end only that the “destinataire,” the receiver of the message, should shave off his hair and look at his head. The message reaches its goal, and Aristagoras the receiver revolts (Herodotos, Histories 5.35). The tattooed head is a protection against torture. If the slave were captured and tortured, he would not himself know the message of revolt. He could not betray his master if questioned and interrogated specifically about his master’s intentions to rise up against those who have enslaved him. He did not know the content of Histiaios’ communication with Aristagoras. But he did know the instructions he bore to Aristagoras, to shave his head and read the message inscribed there. The ruse only displaces the discovery of the message’s truth by a single step, but in this case it succeeds in protecting the message. Here the tattooing, the inscription on the slave’s body, subverts the intention of torture to expose the truth. "Branding": In other contexts in ancient Greece, slave tattooing serves as a sort of label. It is as if writing on the slave body indicated the contents of that body. Such a function of writing recalls the work of Denise Schmandt-Besserat, who argues that writing originates in the markings on the outside of packages recording their contents.3 Aristotle points out in the Politics, as we have seen, that the slave body ought to reveal its truth, ought to be immediately perceptible as a servile body to the eye, but in fact sometimes it is not. A tattoo on a slave reveals his or her true status. In Aristophanes’ Babylonians, of which only fragments remain, we learn that prisoners of war were sometimes branded or inscribed with a mark indicating the city they served.4 [...] though he is a human being, he does not know himself, soon he will know, having this inscription on his forehead. (74_79)6 Herodes invokes the inscription at Delphi, also cited by Plato: gnôthi seauton, “Know yourself.”7 [...] This placement of the “epigram,” whatever it is, if it is that, on the metope, the forehead of the slave, makes the inscription a sign. The message of Herodotos’s slave was concealed by his hair, directed to a specified other, the recipient who received the slave as a vehicle for his master’s words. The communication was not directed to the slave himself. In the case of Herodes’ slave, the man named “Belly” would bear a sign meant to remind him of his humble status. ### Buried Truth If torture helped to manage the troublesome differentiation between slave and free in the ancient city, it also served as a redundant practice reinforcing the dominant notion of the Greeks that truth was an inaccessible, buried secret. In his valuable book Les maîtres de vérité dans la Grèce archaïque, Marcel Detienne describes a historical shift in the Greeks’ ideas about truth that corresponds to the historical shift from mythic to rational thought.1 According to Detienne, Alêtheia is at first conceived of by the Greeks in an ambiguous relationship with Lethe, forgetting; truth is the possession of the poet and the just king, who has access to this truth through memory. Alêtheia is caught up in a relationship of ambiguity with Lêthê because, for example, the poet who speaks truth by using memory also confers truth’s other, forgetfulness, oblivion of pain and sorrow, on his listeners. His “magico-religious” speech, as Detienne calls it, which exists in an ambiguous relationship with truth, persists as the dominant form in the Greek world until the speech of warriors, the citizens who form the city’s phalanxes, a speech of dialogue, comes to dominate the social world in the time of the polis. Detienne associates a resultant secularization of poetic Alêtheia with the name of the poet Simonides. Doxa, seeming, becomes the rival province of sophistic and rhetorical speech, while Alêtheia comes to belong to an unambiguously “philosophico-religious” domain. In this field of discourse the logic of ambiguity typical of the Alêtheia-Lêthê relationship is replaced by a logic of contradiction, in which Alêtheia is opposed to Apatê, deception, as its other. The common use of memory provides a link between these two stages of thinking truth; the secularization of speech marks a break between a mythic and a rationalist semantic field in which the term Alêtheia persists. ### The modern word Tortura A word used in addition to alêthês in the Odyssey is atrekês, real, genuine, with a connotation perhaps of that which does not distort or deviate. The Latin word torqueo means “to twist tightly, to wind or wrap, to subject to torture, especially by the use of the rack.” This word may come from the root trek-, also occurring in Greek, which may give us atraktos, “spindle,” and also “arrow.”6 (Tortor is used as a cult title of Apollo, “perhaps”, according to the Oxford Latin Dictionary, “from the quarter at Rome occupied by the torturers.”)7 Our English word “torture” is taken from this Latin root. The Oxford English Dictionary defines “torture,” an adaptation of the Latin tortura, in the following way: The infliction of excruciating pain, as practised by cruel tyrants, savages, brigands, etc., from the delight in watching the agony of a victim, in hatred or revenge, or as a means of extortion; spec. judicial torture, inflicted by a judicial or quasi-judicial authority, for the purpose of forcing an accused or suspected person to confess, or an unwilling witness to give evidence or information.8 Although the writers of the dictionary list first tyrants, savages, and brigands as the agents of torture, the first entry in their citations of the use of the word in English refers to the Acts of the Privy Council of 1551. This set of connotations, to return to the point, links the English word torture with the twisted, the distorted, and suggests that the truth gained as a confession is in English not conceived of as a straight line, but is rather bent, extorted from time on the rack. In Greek, however, not passing through Latin into English for our etymology (etumos is another word used for “true” in Greek), we have, parallel to atrekês, the word alêtheia with its suggestion of hiddenness and forgetting. The connotations of the alternative words nêmertês and atrekês are respectively “not missing the mark”, and “not deviating from an existing model”; the weight of alêthês rests instead on the trace of something not forgotten, not slipping by unnoticed.9 [...] Even in the texts of the Hippocratic tradition, the body is seen to contain secrets that must be interpreted, elicited by signs that emerge onto the body’s surface, as the emanation from the earth arises to possess the Pythia. [...] Each of these sites of meaning in ancient culture—the epic, oracles, sacred buildings, the medicalized body—lay out a pattern of obscure, hidden truth that must be interpreted. ### Heraclitian truth differs The works of the pre-Socratic philosophers (even to presume to call them philosophers may be to presume too much) present problems of reading for the historian of philosophy, for the literary and cultural critic. Even the problem of who is disciplinarily responsible for these texts is insoluble. And the incompleteness of many pre-Socratic texts causes unease. How can one speak of philosophical development when only one line, one metaphor, one aphorism remains, torn out of context, lines repeated to illustrate a well-known point? The ellipses in the published pre-Socratic fragments recall stopped mouths, messages gone astray, the utter failure of communication across a distance of centuries. [...] The very search for integrity and indivisibility in all things has been called into question by the heirs of Nietzsche, among them those feminists who see the emphasis on wholeness and integrity, on the full body, as a strategy of scholarship that has traditionally excluded the female, who has been identified as different, heterogeneous, disturbing the integrity of the scholarly body, incomplete in herself. Aristotle describes the female as a “deformed” (pepêrômenon) male (Generation of Animals 737a), and argues further that her contribution to reproduction lacks a crucial ingredient, the principle of soul (psukhe). The project of scientific textual studies has been to supply the text’s lack, to reduce the fragmented, partial quality of embodied, material texts, to reject the defective text as it rejects the defective female. Like the slave body that needs the supplement of the basanos to produce truth, the female body and the fragmentary text are both constructed as lacking. [...] Elsewhere Herakleitos seems to argue against an innate hierarchy of mortal beings: “War is father of all, and king of all. He renders some gods, others men; he makes some slaves, others free” (fr. 53). Mortal and immortal status depends on human history, on events. There is no essence, no absolute truth in the differences among beings. Circumstances, history, time affect relations of difference and power.2 This relativism establishes a ground for the vision of equality among citizens in ancient democratic ideology, and even further, a point from which to examine the commonly held view that some human beings are slaves by nature. Herakleitos represents an alternative to the essentializing concept of truth as a buried, hidden substance; he offers a temporal notion of truth, that the basanos of the physician is good at one time, at another time bad, that war creates slaves and free, a relative notion of truth. [...] Herakleitos’s relationship to time, change and process prefigures values of the democracy and of the pre-Socratic sophists whom the aristocratic philosophical tradition despised: “As they step into the same rivers, different and (still) different waters flow upon them” (fr. 12); “we step and do not step into the same rivers; we are and are not” (fr. 49a). His is not a doctrine of superficial appearance and deep truth, but rather a celebration of the mutability and interdependence of all things. The Heraclitean truth, read within his words, fragmentary as they are, celebrating flux, time, difference, allows for an alternative model to a hidden truth. [...] for him truth is process and becoming, obtained through observation, rather than a fixed, divine and immutable truth of eternity. ### Truth and memory The word anagkê, “constraint,” is associated with the yoke of slavery.10 All of human experience suffers from its subjection to necessity; the slave offers an extreme example of the general human condition. In one of her many forms the goddess who instructs the youth, the Kouros, is mistress of “brute force,” or of the bonds associated with enslavement, and is therefore binding the “what-is,” the “true,” in captivity. Like the slave who yields the truth to the torturer, the “what-is” is bound in domination, and delivers up its truth under necessity. [...] Does truth as eternally located elsewhere, either hidden in the body, or hidden in the earth, or hidden inside or beyond human existence, in some realm inaccessible to ordinary consciousness, lead by some tortuous path to the necessity for torture? Can we posit a truth of process and becoming, and another truth of eternity? If so, the word a-lêtheia seems to carry buried within it support for the view of hidden truth, of truth brought up from the depths. The possibility of forgetting leads to the imagination of a buried realm, the realm of forgetting, of Lethe, which can be represented either positively or negatively. It is good to forget suffering and pain, regrettable to forget a message, to forget crucial information that must be transmitted to a listener; in either case Lethe—or, to coin a word, “letheia”—remains a domain beyond consciousness. [...] The dominance of a notion of truth as alêtheia, not forgetting, he attributes in part to the gradual shift to literacy taking place in the fifth and fourth centuries.14 The legal corpus reflects the state of the problem of truth in the fifth and fourth centuries B.C.E. Charles Segal has discussed eloquently the ways in which growing literacy affects concepts of the self and truth in Greek tragedy.15 [...] In the dominant literary and philosophical paradigm, the truth is seen to be forgettable, slipping away from notice, buried, inaccessible, then retrieved through an effort of memory, through the invocation of divine possession, through the interrogation by a privileged seeker of some enlightened source; seeking the truth may involve a journey, a passage through a spatial narrative of some sort, a request, a sinking down into the past, into the interiority of memory. This model of truth seeking is consistent with other such paradigms already suggested earlier, in the law courts, where, as we saw, the violence of the torturer is thought to be necessary to enforce the production of truth from the slave, either to force him or her to recall the truth, or to force him or her to speak the truth for the benefit of the court. The slave’s body is thus construed as one of these sites of truth, like the adyton, the underworld, the interiority of the woman’s body, the elsewhere toward which truth is always slipping, a Utopian space allowing a less mediated, more direct access to truth, where the truth is no longer forgotten, slipping away. The basanos gives the torturer the power to exact from the other, seen as like an oracular space, like the woman’s hystera, like the inside of the earth, the realm of Hades, as other and as therefore in possession of the truth. The truth is thus always elsewhere, always outside the realm of ordinary human experience, of everyday life, secreted in the earth, in the gods, in the woman, in the slave. To recall it from this other place sometimes requires patience, sometimes payment of gifts, sometimes seduction, sometimes violence. ### Torture and commodification Does it have to do with the invention of coinage, with the idea of abstract exchange value, and the slave as an exchangeable body, a thing to be tested like a coin, like a marker for exchange? In the Laws the Athenian says men are like puppets with strings, and that they should follow the soft, golden string, the “golden and hallowed drawing of judgment which goes by the name of the public law of the city” (644-45).